Review: Christophe Buffin de Chosal, The End of Democracy, Translated by Ryan P. Plummer. Printed in the U.S.A.: Tumblar House, 2017.
Introduction
One cannot speak too highly of Christophe Buffin de Chosal’s The End of Democracy. In a fast paced, readable, yet scholarly fashion, Professor Buffin de Chosal* demolishes the ideological justification in which modern democracy rests while he describes the disastrous effects that democratic rule has had on Western societies. He explodes the myth of Democracy as a protector of individual liberty, a prerequisite for economic progress, and a promoter of the higher arts. Once Democracy is seen in this light, a far more accurate interpretation of modern history can be undertaken. The book is a very suitable companion to Hans-Hermann Hoppe’s iconoclastic take down of democracy in Democracy: The God That Failed, released at the beginning of this century. Buffin de Chosal has spoken of a follow up which will be eagerly awaited for.
Democratic Governance
The idea of rule by the people is a scam, one perpetuated by those who, in actuality, are in control of the government. Through the “democratic process” of voting and elections, a small, determined minority can impose its will despite majority opposition:
We often hear it said that ‘in a democracy,it is the people who rule. . . .’ Rule by thepeople is a myth which loses all substanceonce confronted with the real practice indemocracy. [13]
Quoting from a Russian philosopher, Buffin de Chosal continues his criticism:
The best definition [of democracy] wasgiven by the Russian philosopher Vasily Rozanov.‘Democracy is the system by which anorganized minority governs an unorganizedmajority.’ This ‘unorganized majority’ is thepeople, aggregated and individualistic,incapable of reaction because disjointed. [28]
He expands upon Rozanov’s theme:
. . . [C]ontrary to what [democracy’s] principlesproclaim: one can say that the majorityalmost never wins. Democracy is not thesystem of the majority, but that of the mostpowerful minority, and it has this powernot simply due to its numbers, but also andabove all due to its organization. [31]
Power does not reside in “the people” and certainly not in the individual. In democracy, the only way to express one’s preference or protect one’s rights is through the ballot box every so often. “Each voter,” writes Buffin de Chosal, “in a democracy, is the depositary of a tiny particle of sovereignty, in itself unusable. His sole power consists in dropping a ballot into a box, whereby he is immediately dispossessed of his particle of sovereignty at the profit of those who are going to represent him.” [Ibid.]
Popular democracy has always been condemned and feared by most thinkers since the beginning of human societies. It was not until intellectuals saw democracy as a way they could attain power that they began to advocate it as a system of social order. Prior to the democratic age, most of the learned understood that democracy would result in mob rule and the displacement of natural authority with demagogues. In short, the worst would rise to the top as the author describes the characteristics of a contemporary politician:
The ideal politician, on the other hand, ispliable, convincing, and a liar by instinct. He isnot attached to any platform and has noideological objective. The single thing to whichhe is truly committed is power. He wants itsprestige and advantages, and seeks above allto be personally enriched by it. Any politicianwho presents this aspect is recognized as fit forpower in a democracy. . . . It is therefore notsurprising that democratically elected assembliesare almost exclusively comprised ofthese kinds of men and women. Electedheads of state almost always fit this profile,and international institutions, such as theEuropean Union, consider it the onlyacceptable profile. . . . [35]
Democracy and the State
Since the advent of modern democracy, the principle benefactor of its rule has been the State and the politically-connected financial elites who are in actuality the true rulers of societies. Instead of putting an end to the supposedly despotic rule of the Ancien Régime, which Democracy’s proponents claim to have existed throughout the monarchial and aristocratic age, governance by the people, has instead witnessed an increase in state power and control of individual lives to an unprecedented level in human history. Few, if any, pope, emperor, king, prince, or duke have ever possessed such suzerainty.
In contrast to what has been taught in classrooms, on university campuses, and espoused throughout the media, individual rights and freedoms were far better guarded in the age prior to Democracy’s ascendancy. Pre-revolutionary Europe had social structures which insulated individuals from State power far more effectively than under modern democracy:
The concept of an organic society was abolished atthe time of the French Revolution. The corps andorders were suppressed, the privileges were abolished,and everything which allowed the people to protectthemselves from the power of the state was banishedin the name of liberty. [24]
And in return for giving up the order that protected them from state depredations, the people received “sovereignty:”
They were given the false promise that theywould no longer need to defend themselvesfrom the state since they themselves were thestate. But if a people organized into corps andorders are incapable of exercising sovereignty,how much more so a people comprising a formlessmass of individuals! [Ibid.]
Historically, all of the democratic movements which supposedly stemmed from the people were, in fact, a falsehood, perpetuated largely by revolutionaries who sought to replace the established order with themselves. While legislatures, congresses, and democratic bodies of all sorts have been interpreted as the fruition of the masses’ desire for representation, the reality was quite different:
Democracy is not, in its origin, a system ofthe people. In England with the advent of theparliamentary system just as in France during theRevolution, it was not the people who were seenat work. Even the Russian Revolution was not aphenomenon of the people. To regard the peopleor what the communist elegantly call the ‘masses’as the agent of change or political upheaval is purelya theoretical view, a historical myth, of whichone sees no trace in reality. The ‘people’ werethe pretext, the dupes, and almost always thevictims of the revolutions, not the engines. [13]
Not only was propagation of the myth of popular support for democratic ideals propounded for the survival of the new social order, but putting these tenets into practice was accomplished, in large part, by the role of the “intellectual” an often neglected feature of standard historical analysis and the reason behind much social transformation:
The ‘nation’ met the desires of the philosopherswho wanted to transfer power from the monarchto an enlightened, philosophical, and philanthropicclass who, moreover, ought to be financiallycomfortable. The educated bourgeoisie of thetime were the protagonists of this idea, and aportion of the nobility formed their audience. [13-14]
The intellectuals promoted Democracy because it would open up for them considerable opportunities for position and income in the nation state. It must be remembered that it was the intellectuals who justified the idea of Absolutism. Later, the intellectuals turned on the monarchies and sided with the emerging republican classes rightly believing that democratic governance would give them greater opportunities for power in the emerging nation states.
Democracy and Modern History
While most historians see the advancement of democracy and the development of legislative bodies over the course of the last centuries as an advancement in the human condition and one that has emanated from the people’s desire for greater political representation, Buffin de Chosal presents a far different and more accurate interpretation. “Democracy,” he asserts, “is not, in its origin a system of the people.” [13] All of the social movements which eventually led to the destruction of Christendom did not come from the people seeking a greater “voice” in their governance.
“The ‘people,’” he argues, “were the pretext, the dupes, and almost always the victims of the revolutions, not the engines.” [Ibid.] Liberty, Equality and Fraternity was not a popular cry, but one coined and used by the “enlightened” classes to mobilize and justify their overthrow of the French monarchy and with it the destruction of the Church.
The French Revolution was built on theidea of the ‘nation,’ which claimed to bringtogether the intellectual, social, and financialelite of the country. It was on this foundationthat democracy was established and that itfunctioned during almost all of the nineteenthcentury. [Ibid.]
A similar historical narrative can be seen in England.
The rise and eventual triumph of representative democracy in England was not one that percolated from the masses itching for more freedom. “The appearance of the parliamentary system in England,” Buffin de Chosal contends, “was tied to the great movement of Church property confiscation begun under Henry VIII and continuing until the coming of the Stuarts.” [14]
After Henry gorged himself on the Church’s wealth, he sought to bribe as much of the nobility as possible with his ill-gotten gains to insure his power. An envious Parliament, however, wanted its cut of the loot which led to the great internecine struggle between Crown and Parliament which eventually ended in the suzerainty of the latter with the Glorious Revolution of 1688. The real power from then on rested with an oligarchical legislative branch:
The families who had thus helped themselvesto the Church’s goods, morally justified byProtestant ethics, formed the gentry, the classof landowners who sat in Parliament. Parliamentwas not then, as one might believe today, an organof poplar representation. It was an instrumentin the hands of the gentry to defend its own classinterests. [16-17]
That Parliament and the monarchy would become the two dominant ruling structures was the result of the breakdown of the feudal structure which was taking place not only in England, but across Europe. European monarchs continued to gain more and more power at the expense of the feudal landed elite. The gentry’s power and wealth was also on the wane with the rise of commercial centers which most of the time aligned themselves first with the kings and then later with Parliament. The eventual triumph of Parliament, however, did not mean greater democracy for the people:
The financial incentives for England’s adoptionof the Protestant Reformation are thereforeintimately connected with the bolstering ofParliamentary power. The Parliament in Englandwas used to put the monarchy in check and toreplace it with an oligarchic class of wealthyProtestants to whom the kings were required tosubmit. This is why the overthrow of James IIin 1688 was a true revolution. It was not apopular revolution or the overthrowing of atyranny, but it was the rebellion of a classimplementing the transfer of sovereign powerfor its own profit. [17]
The Market Economy
The author takes a refreshing look at the market economy that sets straight the inaccurate and often times hostile analysis of it that frequently comes from conservative circles. He distinguishes and rightly points out that “pure capitalism” or the “unhampered market” is an “excellent thing” [123]. The free market is intimately tied with private property which is a prerequisite for a just society:
[Capitalism] proceeds from respect for private property.As capitalism is the reinvestment or saved money for thepurpose of making new profits, it presupposes respect forproperty rights and free enterprise. It has existed in Europesince the Middle Ages and has contributed significantly tothe development of Western society. [Ibid.]
He insightfully notes that “bad capitalism” often gets lumped in with its “good form” while the latter gets the blame for the baneful excesses of the former. “Monopoly capitalism,” “corporatism,” “the mixed economy,” and “crony capitalism” are not the result of the market process, but stem from “intervention” brought about by the State in favor of its business favorites through participatory democracy. In a truly free market, entrenched wealth is rarely maintained but is constantly subjected to challenges by competitors:
But what one ought to designate as badcapitalism is the concentration of wealth andpower this wealth procures. This danger doesnot stem from capitalism itself but rather fromparliamentary democracy, for it is democracythat enables money powers to dominate thepolitical realm. [Ibid.]
The “monied interest” did not exist under “traditional monarchy,” but was a product of Democracy and the protection and extension of the “bad capitalistic” paradigm that came into being and was expanded by the rise of popular representative bodies. Assemblies, legislatures, and congresses, which emerged, became aligned with the banking and financial interests to bring about the downfall of the monarchies.
The concentration of political power could only be attained after the control of money and credit were centralized in the form of central banking and the gold standard was eliminated. Central banks have been an instrumental part of the democratic age, funding the nation state’s initiatives and enriching the politically- tied financial elites at the expense of everyone else.
Wealth concentration is not a by-product of the free market. Rarely are firms able to maintain their dominance for long periods of time. Many turn to the State to get protection and monopoly grants to ensure their position in the economy:
. . . capitalism only becomes harmful whenit grants political power to the money powers.This was only made possible thanks to the adventof parliamentary democracy, which was aninvention of liberalism. It is therefore thefoundational principles of political liberalism(equality before the law, suppression of privileges,centralization of political power, censitary suffrage,and the accountability of ministers to the legislativehouses) which have enabled the rise of a wealthy classand its power over society. [124]
Such sound economic analysis abounds throughout his tome.
Future Prospects
The author rightly sees that because of its nature and the type of personalities that it attracts, modern democracy cannot reform itself, but will eventually collapse from financial stress, war, and/or civil strife:
Parliamentary democracy rarely produces truestatesmen, as its party system more oftenpromotes ambitious and self-interested persons,demagogues, and even communication experts.These are generally superficial and egocentricindividuals with a very limited understandingof society and man. These politicians do nothave the makings of statesmen. They areadventurers who use the state to satiate theirhunger for power and money or to benefittheir party. [147]
Efforts to reform it, however, should not be totally dismissed since they could lead to more fundamental change and ultimately the creation of a new political paradigm for Western governance. Populism and the various movements around the globe which fall into that category should be encouraged. Populism, because of is lack of definite ideological underpinnings, has meant different things at different times to different people. Most populists, however, do not want to get rid of democratic forms of government, but want the system to be more “responsive” of its constituents instead of favoring entrenched political elites. Populism is a symptom of the growing failure of modern democracy’s inability to “deliver the goods” that it promises to a now growing dependency class.
As a means of getting rid of totalitarian democracy, populist movements and themes should always be encouraged:
In Europe, the only political forces todaywhich could, in the more extreme of circumstancesassume this rescue role are found on the side ofpopulism. Conservative in its values, sometimesclassically liberal when it is a matter of opposingthe stifling interventionism of the state, and yet readyto defend social gains . . . populism is the onlypolitical current which comes to the defense ofthose interests of the population denied or ignoredby the parties in power. [148]
He adds:
Populist parties, from the simple fact that theycan bring together voters from both the leftand the right, have a chance of coming to powerin the near enough future. The deterioration ofsecurity conditions in Europe due to massimmigration plays in their favor. [148-49]
While he does not explicitly discuss it, a more concrete and ideological coherent idea and one of historical precedent, is that of secession. For all those who oppose the democratic order, secession is the most justifiable, logical, and practical strategy for the dissolution of the nation state. Secession movements, therefore, whether they do not outwardly condemn parliamentary democracy and only seek to establish a “better run” system, should always be supported.
Conclusion
The most likely scenario if there is to be a change in Western democratic life will be from a world-wide economic crisis and collapse of the financial system which will render the nation states unable to meet their financial obligations to their citizens. All economies are hopelessly indebted from their welfare state excesses and can never hope to meet their promises which now runs in the trillions. What will emerge in the aftermath of a collapse is hard to predict, but some form of authoritarianism is likely which will be centered on a one-world state with a single, irredeemable currency.
While the financial demise of Western-styled democracy will be evident for all to see, its ideological underpinnings which have justified its existence needs to be extirpated. Any hope of it being reconstituted to better serve “the people” needs to be shot down. There is no better place to start the de-mystification of Democracy than with Christophe Buffin de Chosal’s magnificent, The End of Democracy.
*Professor Christophe Buffin de Chosal teaches economic history at the United Business Institutes.
Antonius Aquinas@antoniusaquinas